The next essay in “Zombies, Vampires and Philosophy” is “The Bloody Connection Between Vampires and Vegetarians” by Wayne Yuen. In it, he is going to argue that it would not be moral for vampires to kill humans for their blood to feed on, and then use that argument that it is also wrong for humans to raise and eat animals for food. I don’t think his argument really works, but in order to get to that argument the first thing he needs to establish is that vampires are indeed moral agents and so can be held morally responsible for their actions. If they were simply animals or were compelled by a strong compulsion to drink human blood, then he’d be unable to establish that vampires would be morally wrong to drink human blood and so any argument he would make for vegetarianism would have to stand on its own without the support of the analogy from vampires. In doing so, he has to talk about the nature of morality and also free will, which is why there’s a fair bit more to talk about in this “Philosophy and Pop Culture” post than there normally is.
So he starts by arguing that in order for us to morally judge vampires, we are going to have to establish that vampires are moral agents and have moral responsibility. He first examines whether they are rational enough to be moral agents, which means, to him, that they can evaluate what the best outcome would be among a host of possibilities and choose on that basis. The issue is this sort of goal-directing reasoning is not sufficient to make someone moral. As I noted in my essay on psychopaths, while they may not make the right choices they certainly seem capable of some sort of goal-based reasoning but have a notable lack in being able to understand what makes a situation a moral one or not, since they fail at the moral/conventional distinction. Yuen tries to establish that they can judge what is and isn’t moral with a quote from one talking about how evil people taste better, but this doesn’t mean that they are able to judge or comprehend what is or isn’t moral but might only reflect that they have learned what humans consider moral or immoral and apply that classification to those people. Since the vampire who says that — Lestat from Interview with a Vampire is not exactly a good being himself it’s far too quick an assessment from that statement that he understands what it really means for someone to be evil. Even if he does, what Yuen would also need to establish is the one thing that we do think that vampires lack when it comes to morality: the capacity to care about what is or isn’t moral. Again, psychopaths can be seen as inherently amoral because they are incapable of being motivated by morality and moral considerations, and vampires in general are seen as lacking that as well. Even if they can judge what is or isn’t moral, they in general are incapable of caring about what is moral or immoral. In Yuen’s example, Lestat’s judgement about evil people is shallow and is unconcerned with their moral status. He neither condemns nor praises their immorality, and seems to only note as an interesting aside or irrelevancy that has an impact on his aesthetic preferences.
So Yuen hasn’t really established that vampires are moral agents because he hasn’t established that they are capable of properly understanding or being motivated by moral considerations. The next issue he tries to address is if they have free will and so can make proper decisions. The big problem here is that while he does seem to get that free will is the ability for us to act on our own choices without being forced to by something outside ourselves, the example he gives is one of coercion: if someone threatens to kill our family unless we do something, Yuen argues that in that case we no longer have the free will to not do that thing. This is, sadly, pretty common in discussions of free will, but is also something that is a philosophical pet peeve of mine. I would agree with Yuen that in such a case we wouldn’t have moral responsibility for taking that action, but argue that it isn’t because we would be forced to do that by something outside of ourselves.
For me, the argument follows on from general Stoic teachings, which argue that if someone threatens your life — or that of your family — in order to force you to do something what the proper Stoic is morally obligated to do is refuse to take that action and let them kill you or your family. The reason is that a person is not morally responsible for what other people do, but is only morally responsible for what they themselves do. So if someone faces such a threat and gives in, then they are still morally responsible for the action they take and so if the action is morally wrong then they did something morally wrong. However, if they refuse to act immorally in the face of such a threat and the other person then kills them or their family, then they are not responsible for what that person did and so have not done anything morally wrong. They are not, therefore, morally responsible for the deaths of their family if they refuse to take that immoral action. All the moral responsibility rests with the person who committed the actual deed themselves.
And outside of what might be considered esoteric philosophical stances, we actually do understand that someone can indeed reasonably and morally choose an action against such strong coercion. In the Shakespeare play “Measure for Measure” (which I just read), a main character is forced by the temporary ruler of the city to either have sex with him or else her brother would be executed. She is adamant that she is forced by morality to choose to let her brother die, and while some people try to encourage her to go through with it to save her brother they understand her position that doing so would be immoral. The war is over practicality vs morality, not over her warped sense of honour vs what is actually moral. Thus, we can understand that it is indeed possible to have an external force apply strong coercive pressure and yet not only be able to choose against that pressure, but in fact to actually be moral — and the most moral — in doing so.
And yet, we also have a strong intuitive understand that if someone had, in fact, given in to that pressure they wouldn’t be held morally responsible for doing so. We would not call such an action immoral, anymore than we generally consider someone who steals food to feed their starving children to have done something immoral. These intuitions, then, are what I think drives the arguments that claim that we cannot be properly responsible for such actions and so can’t freely choose otherwise. I have opined in the past that we don’t necessarily consider their actions moral, but instead consider them understandable. We may consider them taking that action to be them still doing “the wrong thing”, but we can understand why, faced with such a choice, they took that action. This, then, suggests that perhaps the reason we don’t want to consider them morally responsible for that action is because it’s just too much to ask of them to not take that action. Therefore, it’s not that they couldn’t take that action, but that it’s an action that morality cannot reasonably demand they take, and so it ends up being outside of the bounds of morality. We can see this with Utilitarianism where it constantly runs into problems with thought experiments such as you can save your child or a scientist with the cure of cancer from drowning, where utility is clearly on the side of saving the scientist but we all intuitively think that we couldn’t reasonably demand that you sacrifice your child to utility in those cases. There are lots of attempts to patch it up and bring in rules for that and recalculate utility and so on and so forth, but the easier answer might well be that in such strong cases we could not ask someone to actually make that sacrifice. It seems reasonable to argue that a proper moral system cannot force someone to take an action that would break them, and such sacrifices might well break the person making the decision. This, then, might be captured best by Kant’s maxim that we must always treat moral agents as ends in themselves and not merely as a means to an end. That includes as a means to a claim of morality or the demands of a moral system, and such sacrifices treat people as a means to the end of maintaining a moral system.
So it does seem like coercion doesn’t mean that we aren’t morally responsible for our actions, but if the coercion is strong enough we might end up with the decision being taken out of the realm of morality entirely. If vampires are capable of understanding morality and their desire for blood is not a true compulsion, then it does seem like we could assign moral blame to them for killing humans for their blood if that is immoral. And both Yuen and our intuitions claim that vampires killing humans for their blood is morally wrong. Yuen then moves on to argue that while animals are not moral agents, in all relevant respects they are the same as us wrt why we think it is wrong for vampires to kill us for food, and so we ought not kill them for food either. And yet, there is a critical difference: they are not moral agents. It seems reasonable to argue that humans are sentient in a way that animals are not, and so even though animals do suffer it is that extra sentience that makes it so that killing humans for food is immoral. I would disagree that it’s just a matter of rationality, but would argue that it’s about morality. To return to Kant, we are moral agents and so must be treated always as an end in ourselves and not as a means to an end. Animals are not moral agents and so need not be granted that respect.
This doesn’t mean that we can treat them badly. Yuen makes a mistake in arguing that the animals we raise for food are treated poorly in order to make the suffering point, but one can argue that they shouldn’t be made to suffer in that way without accepting that we are not allowed to raise them for food. For example, the above analysis lends itself to an argument that I’ve heard before — but forget the source of — that the reason it is immoral for us to mistreat animals is not because of a moral responsibility we owe to them, but instead because of one that we owe ourselves. Someone who could mistreat animals and deliberately try to cause them to suffer or to be impassive towards their unnecessary suffering is not a good person. They would be missing the virtue of Compassion, or at least it would be deficient in them. Thus, we can tie the Virtue Theory of the Stoics to the deontological theory of Kant and point out that we have no moral obligations to those things that are not moral agents but a virtuous person has traits that will create such obligations internally from their own morally virtuous character. So we would not be a properly moral person if we were apathetic to the unnecessary suffering of animals, but raising and killing them for food need not be that.
Yuen could, of course, argue from this that a moral obligation to not eat animals follows in the same way. However, that … is another argument for another time. So I don’t think that his argument works, mostly because it is a far more wandering path we need to take to negotiate the moral morass to get to where Yuen wants to end up.