So, here it is, Monday again, and I was pondering what to post given that Monday is actually one of my regular posting days (I’ve started adding posts Tuesday and Thursday to take care of the backlog). Sure, curling was on this weekend and so I could have cheated and made that post my Monday post, but that seemed unsatisfying for some reason. But the issue is that I’ve pretty much finished talking about Doctor Who, which is what was filling up the Monday posts before this. Before that, I was posting about the cheap horror movies, but now I post them on Tuesdays, and don’t want to mess with that because I tend to need a quick post for Tuesdays and those posts are pretty quick. I’d post about other movies or the like that I’ve been watching, but I don’t have anything new this week. So, what should I post this week?
And then I remembered my old “Philosophy in Popular Culture” tag. I had decided that I wanted to post more philosophy this year, and had decided that part of that was continuing that series, as it has lagged for quite some time now. Over three years, in fact. Those posts are philosophical and generally relatively quick, so it seemed like a good fit … especially since we got quite a bit of snow over the weekend and so on Sunday, when I was writing this, I was going to have to shovel it and probably wasn’t going to want to do anything else after that.
So, the essay I’m going to look at is from a new book “Dungeons and Dragons and Philosophy”. I had bought this a while ago — probably close to the time I stopped writing these posts — and had decided not to read the book but instead to read it essay by essay when I commented on it. That means that I’ve owned it for likely years and haven’t read anything but the first essay. I may reconsider my stance on reading it. But, anyway, I had read this essay originally and meant to talk about it, never did, and am now returning to it.
The essay is “Sympathy for the Devils: Free Will” by Greg Littmann, and it’s an examination of free will in the context of D&D, and especially in light of the Evil and Always Evil aligned races. Unfortunately, this is the most interesting question — can we really say that races that are “Always Evil” really have a choice in being evil — but he addresses that specific question at the beginning and then dovetails into standard hard determinist arguments against free will, which are both less interesting and more problematic. So I’ll leave the specific problem of “Always Evil” races to the end, and talk about his other points first.
After using the thought experiment of a cleric who slides down a trap and collides with the rogue and having the rogue determine that the cleric had taken an “evil” action in attacking their fellow party member, attempting to show that such blame was unfair (in an attempt to get us to see that calling the evil races evil for what they also have no choice over), Littmann immediately segues into an argument that we are all, in fact, physically determined and so have no choice either. The immediate problem here is that saying that eliminates that entire thought experiment, as we should consider the cleric to have acted just as wrongly by just sliding into the rogue due to the laws of physics as by making an actual decision to attack the rogue. So the rogue’s actions, by that, shouldn’t been seen as unfair and so, by extension, neither should the actions of the party in attacking evil creatures. This, then, should cause us to doubt whether we should have sympathy for the devils at all; perhaps the most reasonable action is simply to treat any action that harms others except as direct retribution or attempt to prevent hard as evil and react accordingly, even the thought experiment with the cleric. More philosophically, we can note that the difference between the cleric falling and the cleric attacking is a fact about the internal state of the cleric, specifically about intentions. If intentions and determinism are not compatible, then his thought experiment doesn’t work under the deterministic view that he purports to hold.
Which leads to where he goes next, which is to talk about compatiblism. He invents another thought experiment to attack them: imagine that a succubus has “seduced” the fighter and made him attack the party, and the party, once he is freed, decides to execute the fighter in response because the fighter attacked the party. Using the definition of compatiblism that says that it is about acting on your desires, he says that holding the fighter responsible seems unfair, but since all desires are equally determined we are all in that situation all the time, so it isn’t fair to hold us responsible either. The problem is that, again, he bases this on an idea that forces us to distinguish between the internal motivations of the person, and even worse is one that compatiblists — the group he is going after — have already taken into account. Most compatiblists who deal with decision-making argue that a free choice is one that is made from a person’s decision-making capacity when that capacity is functioning properly. If the succubus is exerting exceptional influence over the fighter’s mind, then the fighter’s decision-making capacities are either not involved in the decision or are not functioning properly. Thus, he shouldn’t be held accountable for attacking the party. But if he had decided to attack them based on fully functioning capacities, then he should be held responsible for his actions. Littmann’s example relies on us having this distinction in mind, applying what we think we should do for what we consider “free” decisions to the case that we don’t think is “free”, pointing out how unfair that would be, and then trying to apply that back to the “free” choice, arguing that the “free” choice is no more free than that one. But we could just as easily decide that we were wrong to think that in the case that was not “free” it would be unfair to “punish” them. Littmann’s gives no reason for us to think that that solution is any less reasonable than the one he advocates.
This only gets worse when he makes the same sort of argument that Jerry Coyne does about the consequences of his arguments: we cannot justify retribution, but instead can only justify causing suffering on the basis of rehabilitation or preventing others from causing suffering. Putting aside that changing our thoughts on the matter requires our internal thought producing systems to not be deterministic and so be “free” which is what he had to deny to make his other arguments work, the question we can ask here is: why not? Is there any meaningful concept of evil without people being able to have meaningful intentions, for good or evil? If we can’t claim that the evil races are evil because they aren’t free, then how would it be in any way evil to kill them for the harms they cause or, in fact, for any reason we want? Why should we think that we are only “allowed” to cause suffering if it will prevent suffering? Sure, that was how we defined good and evil before, but that, as Littmann argues, is determined by and embroiled in our idea that the choices are free and that intentions matter. If our choices aren’t free and intentions don’t matter, then what we do and why we do it don’t matter either. So why stick with the outdated idea of morality that Littmann rejects or, rather, why should we reject the things he rejects and accept the things that he wants to accept?
I’ll skip the discussion of how things being random don’t save free will, but will now backtrack a bit and talk about his idea that, following on from Einstein, the future is fixed and so we can’t have any kind of meaningful free will. Compatiblists who tie it to decision-making processes, of course, don’t have an issue here, but even without that this isn’t as clear as Littmann thinks it is. I like to use this thought experiment: imagine that I have a time machine, and I go into the future, observe the outcome of your free choice, and then return. Even if that was by that necessitated to happen, would that automatically make it not a free choice? Well, no, it would seem that by definition it would still be a free choice, because my simply coming to know what that choice was going to be had no causal impact on your decision-making process. Even under determinism, there is no way that my coming to know that could causally impact that process, and so it can’t impact that process and that choice one way or the other. And this would seem to hold to free choices as well; there is no causal mechanism that could impact that. You could reply that my thought experiment isn’t possible if we have free will as the future could never be determined beforehand, but this gets into complicated ideas about time travel that are too long to get into here. Suffice it to say, his argument isn’t as clear as he thinks it is.
It doesn’t help that he himself provides a counter-example to his own argument: that of randomness. He implies that randomness is still randomness under such a system, and that there’d still merely be a fact about what that random process spit out. Well, then why wouldn’t the same thing be true of free choices: the choices are free, but there’s a fact of the matter about what free choice was made. So that argument doesn’t really do for him what he hopes it will.
So let’s return to the more interesting example: what do we do about creatures who by their nature are evil and so don’t really get to choose whether to act evil or not? Well, there are two basic way to look at them. First, we can see them as having evil desires by nature that predisposes them to act evil. As long as it is possible for them to act on other desires and so not act evil, then we can rightly punish them for acting evil. However, if they are literally incapable of acting on any other desires or not in an evil fashion, then they seem more like a force of nature than like a person, and so we might be able to justify killing them simply on the basis that it is not possible for them to do otherwise and we want them to stop harming other people. So the stronger Littmann’s case is that they cannot freely choose to do evil, the more we should be inclined to say that we should take dramatic steps to prevent them from committing evil, which would then justify the “Detect and kill” paladin: anything that comes up as “Likely to harm others” — the only meaningful notion of “Evil” that Littmann allows — should just be killed out of hand to prevent that. As they are not free, there are no other options. But don’t blame us for it: we aren’t free either.
Arguments against free will tend to rely on free will presumptions to make their case, and Littmann’s essay is no exception to that. And one of the main issues with hard determinism that is responsible for the existence and possibility of compatiblism is that their conclusions, if they hold strictly to them, seem so counter-intuitive that they simply cannot be true. But if they weaken their conclusions, then they seem like compatiblists who simply don’t want to admit it, which is pretty much true of Coyne much of the time. Free will, then, seems far more complicated than most hard determinists will allow.
Thoughts on “The Exiles Trilogy”
January 31, 2019Continuing my reading of all the Ben Bova fictional novels I own, the next one is “The Exiles Trilogy”, a collection of the entire trilogy of … novels, I guess, although they’re closer to novella length than novel length in my opinion. Anyway, the linking theme of them is a group of geneticists and rocket scientists are exiled to a space station because their research is seen as a threat to the stability of the world, and so they decide to convert the space station into an interstellar craft and leave Earth instead, to the somewhat blessing of the Earth government. The first work details them being exiled and converting the space station, the second work details them arriving at the first planet, and the last work details them finally settling in on the planet they are going to inhabit. As this is a Ben Bova work and he tends towards harder science-fiction than others, there is no faster-than-light drive and so each work focuses on a different generation of people as they take the years and years to get to where they were going.
All three of them are standard Ben Bova works, for good or for ill. The good is that Bova tends to build interesting worlds and situations, but unfortunately here that’s done the best in the first book and is uninteresting in the second book. While the World Government exiling many of its best scientists isn’t particularly credible, Bova does manage to present a world there where instability is avoided through sheer force of order, and there is an explanation given for why they see them as too much of a threat, even though “Not everyone will be able to go!” isn’t a particularly good one for the rocket scientists, who have to be exiled as well to make the plan work. The second work, however, sticks to a mostly standard set-up, and the third work reverts to a society run by and populated only by children, following on from disagreements that caused the adults to kill each other. The former is rather dull as a world, and the latter is somewhat nonsensical given the previous two works and so seems to only exist to create the specific situation that Bova is exploring there.
Unfortunately, the standard flawed character drama still exists, including the moustache-twirling villains and the love triangles. Again, the first work works best, as the head of the World Government is at least a bit sympathetic even as some of the other members are standard villains, and the love triangle, though contrived, makes some sense. The problem here, though, is that it centres on the female character not being sure about wanting to be exiled and having issues with that, which while understandable is something that drags down the plot in a number of ways, especially when she ends up being incredibly cold to the male lead because of it, which makes her a bit unsympathetic, as if she hated being dragged into that so much she could simply take the opportunity given to her to leave. In the second work, the villain at least changes, but it changes into one part of the triangle being insane, despite the efforts to hide that fact. In fact, the efforts to hide that fact hurt it when we find out the truth because it makes things seem far more contrived and pointless. Additionally, the female part of the triangle here comes across as an unsympathetic character because she starts with a Lady Macbeth sort of role: encouraging the other member of the triangle to push the other man out of the leadership despite that being their agreement and saying that she loves him more than the other despite her being arranged to marry him and so promises to marry him instead of the other one if he does so. And then she spends the rest of the work refusing to commit to either of them, and the only interesting thing she does is set a trap to catch the person who killed her father due to the disagreement over whether to stay or move on to another planet. The third work is even worse, as the second part of the triangle is a moustache-twirling, power-mad villain whom the female part of the triangle has no reason to be interested in and is portrayed as not being interested in, and she herself does a number of stupid things either out of a desire for power or out of fear that cause problems for everyone involved, and the work isn’t clear about her motivations in these cases. The love triangle here is pointless and the villain idiotic and incompetent.
Overall, again, typical Ben Bova works, with the typical Bova virtues and flaws. The first work is actually reasonably entertaining, but the last two suffer greatly, as the best parts are the things that were done so much better in the first work and the worst parts are just bad. It’s unlikely I’ll ever read the entire trilogy again, which means that I’m unlikely to read the first work again because it is combined with the other two. Still, it could have been worse, as it was interesting enough and at least the three works combined worked out to about the length of a solid novel, which means that they were short.
Posted in Books, Not-So-Casual Commentary | Leave a Comment »